4 Greek and Roman Conceptions of Natural Law
Mrs. Suman Dash BhatMishra
Introduction:
Modern conceptions of Law and Justice owe a lot to the ancient philosophers of Greece and Rome in content and approach. Modern notions of equality, equal application of laws, human rights and sovereignty are incomplete without an understanding of Natural Law, which is inherent in all laws and is the litmus test for determining the legitimacy of every law. Natural Law is ubiquitous and is applicable to all without distinctions of caste, creed, gender, geography and other such parameters. An understanding of the evolution of natural law is necessary to study the growth of Law as it exists today, across civilisations and cultures and the only way to do so is to begin with the origins of Natural Law in early Greek and Roman societies.
Greeks and their Conception of Natural Law:
Greeks were the earliest to have a conception of Natural Law principles.1 That there exist universal principles which govern the cosmos and are applicable to all human beings without discrimination was discerned by the Greeks in their philosophical pursuits concerning social norms, human society and moral values.2 They were also the first among peoples all over the world to shape law as an entity distinct and separate from mere blind faith or a set of religious rites.3 Their theories of law and justice underwent a long and arduous journey- a journey that has best been described in the words of W. Friedmann as a ‘search for absolute values’.4 The very first contours of Natural Law were drawn, in and around the 5 th century B.C., by an enlightened group of Greek philosophers- the Sophists, who conceived of Nature as not just a substance but a relation, an order of things.5 The era of Sophists was followed by Stoics, who gave a completely different dimension to the idea of Natural Law.
Evolution of Principles of Natural Law among the Sophists:
The fifth century B.C. witnessed a massive transformation in Greek philosophy, with the emphasis of Greek philosophers shifting from ancient, traditional values. The phenomenal rise of the Sophists, who identified Law as a purely human invention born out of necessity, detached from metaphysics and alterable at will, was witnessed in this era.6 This rationalisation of Law and Justice was triggered by the prevalent social circumstances of Greece which witnessed frequent changes in the laws in the city states of the democratic republic.
The Sophists questioned the reasons behind such frequent changes in laws and while pondering over their validity arrived at the conclusion that natural law is different from and opposed to, written law.7 For instance, Sophocles, in his magnum opus, Antigone, states that natural or divine law is wise while written law is arbitrary.8 One of the chief proponents of Sophism, Heraclitus conceived of Nature as a rhythm of events.9 For the first time, Nature was identified as a concept beyond matter or substance and was seen as an entity which is a relation, an order of things.10 This realisation of Nature as an existing superior entity, lent strength to the idea of Natural justice which, according to the Sophists, was a body of permanent, unchangeable, non-negotiable rules which were never arbitrary and always applicable equally to all human beings.
The Sophist philosopher Callicles, also propagated the idea of natural justice in similar lines. The principle of “right of the strong” was stressed by him.11 He proclaimed that in nature, the strong prevail over the weak but human laws are designed to protect the weak and bring about equality among all human beings, which in essence is against the fundamental law of Nature. This is because in nature, inequality has been created by giving different measures of strength to every member of the human and animal species and in both societies the law
1 M.D.A. Freeman, Lloyd’s Introduction to Jurisprudence (Sweet and Maxwell 2007 )97
2 Ibid.
3 W. Friedmann , Legal Theory (Fifth Edition, Universal Law Publishing Co. 2008) 98
4 ibid
5 ibid.
6 Edgar Bodenheimer, Jurisprudence The Philosophy and Method of the Law (Sixth Indian Reprint Universal Law Publishing Co. Ltd. 2009) 43
7 Friedmann (n3) 98
8 Sushila Ramaswamy, Political Theory: Ideas and Concepts (Fifth Reprint Macmillan India Ltd. 2008) 285-89
9 ibid
10ibid
11ibid
of nature proclaims that the strong should prevail over the weak.12 Similarly, Thrasymachus emphasised that Law was a weapon created by the strong and the mighty to promote their own advantage.13 He further emphasised that the path of injustice is much more rewarding than the path of justice and it pays to act unjustly, if one can get away with it.14
Plato’s Contribution to the Theory of Natural Law:
The rise of Socrates is perhaps the most interesting chapter in Greek philosophy. Socrates, along with Plato, was able to spread the idea that the notion of Justice was miscalculated by Thrasymachus and other early Sophist thinkers. He also argued that such notions of Law and Justice would endanger the moral fabric of society and create more chaos than harmony, more insecurity than security, thus causing social degeneration from within and without. Plato based his philosophy on the teachings of Socrates. His ideas of Law and Justice revolved around his fundamental belief in the innate inequality of human beings. Plato opined that Nature has endowed human beings with varying degrees of capacity.15 On this premise, he justified the creation and continuity of a Class system in society based on division of Labour.16 According to him, the objective of human life was to deliver the specific functions which a human being was expected to discharge as per his capacity.17 Justice, according to him, was to keep to one’s work without interfering with that of others. Thus, Plato divided men into four sections: Gold, Silver, Copper and Iron.
The first class of people was supposed to be the ruling class whereas the second class was concerned with defence or military activities. People belonging to the first two classes were required to shun all indulgences of private life including the right to create a family and acquire private property.18 In the first two classes, union of men and women was required to be temporary as the focus of these classes was to protect the State and discharge functions that would serve public good. On the other hand, the last two classes, i.e. Iron and Copper were supposed to be the producing class. Together, they constituted the largest class of the society and were permitted to form families and maintain private property19. Further, Plato’s philosophy is characterised by a strong dislike for Law. In “The Republic”, Plato advocates that justice should be administered without law as according to him, Law is a body of abstract and simple principles, not suitable for application to complex situations of life.20 It is on this ground that Plato preferred the administration of justice by a wise man trained in kingship to the authority of Law.
Aristotle’s Idea of Natural Law:
Like his predecessors, Plato’s pupil, Aristotle also made a significant contribution to the domain of Natural Law. However, unlike Plato, Aristotle’s perception of the Law was based on a deep and pragmatic understanding of human nature. Aristotle believed that Plato’s conception of justice demanded exceptional nobility from individuals which was the very antithesis of average human nature.21 He conceived of man as a part of nature, as an animal endowed with one strikingly unique feature: Rationality. Man according to Aristotle, was the
12ibid
13 Julius Stone, Human Law and Human Justice(Universal Law Publishing Co. 2008) 11-15
14 ibid.
15 G.W. Paton, A Textbook of Jurisprudence (Oxford University Press 2007) 99-119
16 ibid.
17 ibid.
18 David Boucher and Paul Kelly, Political Thinkers from Socrates to the Present,(Oxford University Press) 29-
42
19Brian R. Nelson, Western Political Thought (Pearson Education 2006) 51-68
20ibid
21ibid
best of animals when he was controlled by law, but his segregation from laws, made him the worst of all beings in nature.22 He opined that it is the Law which must be treated as supreme and not individuals since no human being is above the pollution of vices that come with untrammelled power and pride. Aristotle identified Natural Justice as a body of those principles which could not be altered and had the same validity everywhere. The legitimacy of these principles did not depend on their acceptance or non-acceptance by any segment of society or individuals. In contrast to this, Aristotle also evolved the conception of Conventional Justice which was capable of variations and alterations. As one can see, Aristotle marked the beginning of a significant qualitative change in the content of Greek philosophy: a change from Idealism to Realism, from abstraction to concreteness, from radical arguments to a state of balance in the idea of Law and Justice.
Fundamental principles of noted Sophist Scholars:
Rise of the Stoics and their Idea of the Law of Nature:
Aristotle’s conception of Law and his emphasis on Man’s Reason in the “Logic” shaped the Stoic’s philosophy of Justice. The Stoic school of thought was led by Zeno.23 Zeno and his
22ibid
23http://www.thenagain.info/WebChron/WestCiv/Stoicism.html accessed 13 November 2014
followers were pantheists who identified Nature with God. According to them, Law could be conceived only with Nature at the centre. Stoics advocated for unity of all human beings and believed that law prevails in Human Reason. According to them, all human beings are equal and laws therefore, are applicable to all equally. They propagated a cosmopolitan philosophy where distinctions between all city-states would pale into oblivion. The Stoics built their philosophy on the premise that Natural Laws have universal validity and are not capable of change in any part of the world.
Peculiarity of Roman Legal System
After the Greeks, it was the turn of Romans to inquire into the domain of Nature, Law and Justice. They were inspired heavily by the Greeks, particularly the philosophy of the Stoics and attempted to give shape to the hitherto abstract forms of Law and Justice.
In order to appreciate the positioning of natural law in ancient Rome, we need to distinguish with clarity amongst three simultaneous concepts in vogue in the Roman Legal System. The first one is jus civile which refers to the Civil law of Rome. It was meant for the citizens of Rome alone and was not applied to non-citizens. Jus gentium referred to a body of principles applied to non-citizens. It reflected the common principles found across legal systems. Jus naturale refers literally to natural law though it carried different connotations in the writing of different philosophers.
Jus civile
As stated above, it referred to the civil law of Rome applied specifically and categorically to Roman citizens. It was the positive law of the land enacted by the legislative authority.24
Jus gentium
24Gaius in Institutes Bodenheimer 15; “For whatever law any people has established for itself is peculiar to that State and is called the jus civile, as being particular law of that state.”
The Roman empire was vast and consisted of a heterogeneous population. Jus Civile, or the Civil Law, was applicable to Roman citizens. However, the Roman empire consisted of a huge number of non-Roman people who were used to their own set of customs, rules and practices. The judicial magistrates administering the law found it unfeasible to apply the Roman civil law to the people from foreign lands.25 The very conception of jus civile was state specific and thus was not considered a proper law to be applied to those who were not citizens of the state. They also found it beyond them to apply the foreign law of the parties in cases before them.26 This necessitated the development of rules which could be uniformly applied to this diverse population in similar factual contexts.
Though the magistrates could not apply the foreign laws directly, they utilised the content of these various foreign laws to decipher some common principles and unify the application of rules across the variety of population living in Rome.27 The process of creating these general principles was more inductive than deductive.28 The magistrates progressed from various individual cases to general principles.29 This body of principles came to be known as jus gentium or “law of the nations”.
It has to be seen here that evolution of jus gentium Roman Empire can be traced back more to the peculiarities of the Roman legal system than to a clear philosophical proposition. The legal system of Roman empire, in terms of its functioning has often been compared to the later English system.30 It was not a system based on well debated philosophies or abstract theories. The legal principles which came to prevail were not deduced from general principles of law. The process was primarily inductive in nature. The general principles evolved out of particular applications of logic and reason in individual cases. The legal system responded to the needs of actual cases and over a course of time, a collective of such recorded applications of rules emerged as a generalised principles of law.
This body of general principles was not perceived as a higher body of principles. It was more in the nature of common principles prevalent in the laws and usages of different communities which reflected a sense of right common to all.31 Gaius dissects the nature of jus gentium as one informed with the natural reason common in all men.32
Jus naturale
25Friedmann 101; “The ancient idea of citizenship made it impossible to apply Roman civil law to foreigners.”
26 Friedmann 101; “Nor could Roman magistrates apply foreign law as such.”
27 Friedmann 101; “… they could take, from the material supplied by foreign laws and customs, those which appeared capable of general application, such as maritime and other commercial usages, greatly developed among the seafaring people on the Mediterranean, and they could mould them into general principles.”
28Bodenheimer 16; “Whenever a particular rule or usage was observed by the Romans to be practiced by a large number of other nations, it was incorporated into the jus gentium.”
29 Friedmann 101; “Roman magistrates developed these general principles of justice and reason empirically from case to case, not by deduction from a general idea.”
30 Friedmann 102; “Roman legal development, as later English legal development, was a gradual adaptation to new needs and the infiltration of new ideas through practical experiment. The development occurred through the judicial process.”
31 Friedmann 101; “What they created was not directly a body of natural law principles, but the jus gentium as the embodiment of the law and usages observed among different peoples, and representing general good sense.”
32 Gaius in Institutes Bodenheimer 15; “All nations who are ruled by law and customs make use partly of their own law and, partly of that which is common to all men. …. But whatever natural reason has established among all men is equally observed by all mankind, and is called jus gentium, because it is the law which all nations employ.”
The term ‘natural law’ or just naturale has in the context of the Roman legal system has to be understood in two perspectives. One was in the sense of a higher order of principles providing a validating yardstick for the positive law made by men. The most vocal expression of this perspective can be seen in the works of Cicero. In the other sense, which is used by many Roman jurists, it reflected not a universal law of higher order, but a reasonable proposition oriented towards the solution of a given case.33 In its later sense, natural law represented a prima facie reasonable proposition rather than an enlightened rationality.34
Cicero (106-43 B.C.)
The most prominent of Roman scholars whose work contributed to the idea of natural law was Cicero. Like the Stoic philosophers, Cicero considered the faculty of reason as the fulcrum of the universe.35
He identified True Law as reason in conformity with nature. He contended it to be of universal application and of immutable character. The nature of this law was to be beyond the confines of countries and societies.36 He invested law with the force of nature as designed by divine dispensation. This element of reason, present in intelligent men37 was the parameter for the justness of an act.38 The faculty of reason in every man ensures that a sense of justice is inherent in human nature.39 He was categorical in his view that natural law presented us with a yardstick to judge the validity of positive law enacted by any ruler, however legitimate.40
Evolution Through Natural Law
The Roman philosophers are usually not credited with any original principle or philosophy of natural law developed by them. Even much of what Cicero says is only a reaffirmation of principles developed in Stoic philosophy. The greatest contribution of the Roman lies in the gradual implementation of natural law principles41 into the jus civile and jus gentium through
33 Bodenheimer 15; “Although the legal texts of the classical epoch abound with references to jus naturale naturalis ratio and natura rerum, the “natural law” envisaged in these texts is usually not the universal and supratemporal law discussed by Cicero, but rather represents a proposed solution of a case which is in accord with the expected conduct of men in Roman society or with the inherent justice of a particular factual situation.”
34 Bodenheimer 15; citing Ernst Levy; “Natural was to them not only what followed from physical qualities of men or things, but also what, within the framework of the legal system, seemed to square with a normal and reasonable order of human interests and, for this reason, need not be in need of any further evidence.”
35 Bodenheimer 13; “Cicero (106-43 B.C.) the great Roman lawyer and statesman, was strongly influenced by the ideas of the Stoic philosophers. Like them, he was inclined to identify nature and reason and to assume that reason was the dominating force in the universe.”
36 Cicero, De Re Publica, Bodenheimer 14; “And there will not be different laws at Rome and at Athens, or different laws now and in the future, but one eternal and unchangeable law will be valid for all nations and at all times and there will be one master and ruler, that is God, over us all, for he is the author of this law, its promulgator, and its enforcing judge.”
37 Bodenheimer 14; “To Cicero, the sense of justice, though capable of growth and refinement, was a universal possession of all reasonable men.”
38Bodenheimer 14; “In ascribing “natural force” to the law, Cicero made it clear that the mind and reason of the intelligent man was the standard by which justice and injustice were to be measured.”
39Bodenheimer 14; “Justice is therefore inherent in nature (understood as human nature)…”
40 Friedmann 102; “Was jus natural for the Romans a higher law by which the validity of positive law was measured? For Cicero, it emphatically has that function. Friedmann cites Cicero—- ; “It is not allowable to alter this law nor deviate from it, nor can it be abrogated. Nor can we be released from this law, either by the Senate or by the people.”
41 Friedmann 102; “At no other time has the ideal of natural law exercised as creative and constructive an influence.”
sustained creativity.42 More than jus civile, reformations in relation to which took much longer time, various principles of natural law manifested themselves through the instrumentality of jus gentium.43 There was no separate sphere of law recognised as jus naturale but the principles of jus naturale as recognised under the Stoic philosophy found expression in the shaping and moulding of jus gentium.44
As has been noted earlier, the Roman legal system thrived not on philosophical inclinations but on the basis of requirements in actual individual cases as they emerged. Thus, apart from Cicero, not many indulged in the philosophical debate as to the requirement of jus civile or jus gentium to conform to a higher order of jus naturale.45 The legal system evolved through sustained and vigorous application of natural law doctrines in individual cases, not through a philosophical dialogue on the supremacy of natural law.46
Impact of this application of natural law principles to reshape the value orientation of law can be seen in several areas like the amelioration of slaves and the reformulation of family relations.47 The principle of equality as a fundamental Stoic philosophy has significant impact on the adaption of positive law to propositions which were more harmonious to such a principle.48 This can be seen in successive reforms which were directed at providing more humane legal conditions to slaves.49 A similar evolution can also be seen in the progressive improvement in the legal position of wives vis-à-vis their husbands. From being under absolute and complete control of their husbands and having no proper claims or rights against the husbands, the wives acquired a progressive status of independence over a course of time.50 Similar trends, though much more gradual and tedious in terms of the transformation, can be seen in the contours of legal relations between a father and his children. The extent of control at one point of time extended to the right of a father to force his grown up sons/daughters to divorce their spouse. Such autocratic and absolutist elements of control were gradually decimated through constant infusion of humanitarian principles based on equality of human beings.
Difference between Greek and Roman Schools of Thought: Concluding Remarks
It is interesting to note that a very strong difference prevailed between the Greek and Roman schools of Natural Law. Although both of them believed in the existence of universal principles, the Greeks believed in the existence of an absolute ideal. Their idealism pervades
42 Friedmann 102; “Natural Law, apart from transforming the old jus civile, now created the basis on which Roman and foreign people could live together under a common rule of law.”
43Friedmann 101; “Gradually, not only the sphere of application, but the meaning of jus gentium widened.”
44Friedmann 102; “After the jus naturale has exercised its creative function through the agency of jus gentium it became expect when, at a later period, Stoic philosophy was received by a civilized and disillusioned generation which dictators had ousted from politics, and which found its refuge is philosophy.”
45 Bodenheimer 15; “Many of the famous Roman jurists of the classical epoch of Roman Law (which lasted from the first century B.C. to the middle of the third century A.D.) were likewise under the influence of the Stoic philosophy. However, the work of these men was largely of a practical nature, and they had little occasion to engage in abstract theoretical discussion about the nature of law and justice.”
46 Friedmann 102; “Moreover, through being part of jus gentium , most natural law precepts were part of positive law. On the whole, the problem of jus natural as a higher law invalidating incompatible positive law did not trouble Roman lawyers much since there was no conflict of law-giving authorities as there was later.”
47Friedmann 102
48At the same time, it would be a stretch to suggest that these legal developments owed their inspiration entirely to the influence of Stoic philosophy. A variety of factors went into the these changes. However, the fact remains that the Stoic philosophy played an important role in realigning the value orientation of people towards a more equal state of social conditions. See Bodenheimer 17-19
49Bodenheimer 17
50 Bodenheimer 17
their philosophy in all its manifestations. The absolute ideal acquired various perceptions but no conclusion could be reached in relation to its exact composition. What remained is a combination of ideas that emerged from the journey towards perfection which by themselves could not be integrated with social life. On the other hand, the Romans followed a more pragmatic approach towards the law. Consequently, Natural Law evolved from an interaction of the law with social institutions.
Summary
- The Greek school of thought can be divided into two primary offshoots: Sophists and Stoics.
- Socrates, Aristotle, Plato have contributed significantly to ancient conceptions of Natural Law.
- Among Romans, Cicero was the fore-runner of Natural Law philosophy and Romans are credited for following a more pragmatic approach towards the content of Natural Law.
- The crystallisation of law into jus civile, jus gentium and jus naturale is a contribution of the Romans.
you can view video on Greek and Roman Conceptions of Natural Law |